|
Smith has several reasons for
criticising this typology. First of all because of its geopolitical dimension which
overlooks the influence of both kinds of nationalisms in different European communities:
the organic version in Ireland and later 19th century France, the rational ideal in some
versions of Czech, Hungarian and Zionist nationalism, as well as in early West African
nationalisms (Smith 1991, p.81). Furthermore the western nationalisms owe much to the
earlier monarchies (as seen as well in Andersons chapter on official
nationalism, where the old monarchies of Europe tried to legitimise themselves by
naturalisation (Anderson 1983, p.86-87)). Finally Smith states that there
should be made a distinction between German and Italian nationalisms opposed to the
relatively underdeveloped Balkan and Eastern Europe. But despite these criticisms, Smith
finds Kohns distinction between a more rational and a more organic version valid and
useful. But it is important, he stresses, that both models can be found in the
East and in the West, in Asia, Africa, and Latin America, and as a
mixture with greater or lesser emphasis on one or the other (Smith 1991, p.79-82). Like Smith I also find it appropriate for
analytical purposes to describe the two different (in a Weberian understanding) ideal
types of the nation, the cultural or organic and the political or the civic. As seen in
the figure below: Fig.
2:[2]
In this way the organic-cultural
notion of the nation has as its basic assertion that the nation should be defined on the
basis of ethnic criteria, and that every nation, ethnically defined, should be gathered in
their own state. Contrary to this, the political-civic notion of the nation has as its
basic assertion that everyone that lives within the boundaries of the state should become
a part of the nation, which is what lies in the concept of nation-building. Both
principles then stress the cultural similarity of their adherents but in fundamentally
different manners. The political-civic in an inclusive way and the organic-cultural in an
exclusive way. Let us now turn to look a little bit
closer at the different aspects of the phenomenon, as they are described by the different
theories, and in this way see that this distinction is also reflected in the different
views of nationalism. The typology I will return to later. 2.2 Nationalism as a Political
Doctrine
Some authors view nationalism as a
political phenomenon legitimising actions or systems. In this way nationalism is primarily
viewed as a political principle, which holds that the political and the national
unit should be congruent (Gellner 1983, p.1 and Hobsbawm 1990, p.9). According to
this view the nation and nationalism can only be understood in relation to a certain kind
of modern territorial state; the nation-state. In this understanding the state plays a
central role in the process of building the nation. As Hobsbawm writes: It is the
state which makes the nation and not the nation the state (Hobsbawm 1990, p.44-45).
Nations and nationalism are hence in this perspective seen as something constructed mainly
from above. In this respect it is interesting to see
that both Gellner and Hobsbawm, refuses a fixed definition of the nation (Gellner 1983,
p.6-7 and Hobsbawm 1990, p.7-10). According to Hobsbawm the question ought not to be
what is the nation? but rather what has the notion - the nation - meant
in different, often competitive, contexts, in different periods, for different groups with
different political strategies? Hobsbawm generally sees the national
question as situated at the point of intersection of politics, technology and social
transformation. He states that nationalism should be seen as something essentially
constructed from above but not only as that. According to Hobsbawm, it is also necessary
to analyse it from below. Thus he criticises Gellner for being to one-sided, making it
difficult to analyse nationalism from below, in terms of the assumptions and feelings of
the ordinary people. However, although Hobsbawm mentions this duality of nationalism, he
is mostly concerned with analysing nationalism from above and neglects to analyse it from
below. Anderson deals in his book with what he
calls official nationalism. Originally it is something that should be
understood in connection to the decline of the monarchies of Western Europe, during which
nationalism could function as legitimising the continuation of dynastic rule. The purpose
was to unite dynasty and subjects. The king was no longer ruling as Gods
representative on earth, but now as a number one among his fellow countrymen. In this way
official nationalism was used to make the king a symbol of the nation. Furthermore the
official nationalism developed after, and in response to the national/popular movements,
the aim of the official nationalism being not only to legitimise the king, but also the
empire, as Anderson writes: These official nationalisms can best be
understood as a means for combining naturalisation with retention of dynastic power, in
particular over the huge polyglot domains accumulated since Middle Ages, or, to put it
another way, for stretching the short, tight, skin of the nation over the gigantic body of
the empire (Anderson 1983, p.86). What is important here is that Anderson
have a layer upon layer conception of nationalism, so that the different nationalisms that
he speaks of (Creole nationalism, vernacular nationalism, etc.), can be copied, refined
and mixed and then be used differently, depending on time, place and the concrete
contents. In this way official nationalism can be seen as a model used for its
manipulating abilities by those who are in control of the political apparatus,
as he writes: The one persistent feature of this style of nationalism was, and is,
that it is official - i.e. something emanating from the state, and serving the
interests of the state first and foremost (Anderson 1983, p.159). In this way you
can state that Anderson also (but not only as we shall see) view nationalism as a
political doctrine, legitimising actions or systems. An extreme, but nevertheless fruitful,
version of viewing nationalism as something political we find at Paul R. Brass. He
understands basically nationalism as something political. As a social and political
creation by elites, whereby ethnic groups, or rather their elites, uses ethnic/national
identity when it comes to put forward demands on the political or economical level to
obtain political power or economic gains. A modern phenomenon inseparably connected to the
activities of the modern centralising state. Brass sees two ways in which nations can
be created. Either by the transformation of an ethnic group to a self-consciousness
political identity in a multi-ethnic state or by the fusion of different ethnic groups
creating a homogenous national culture by the modern state as promoter. An ethnic group he
defines as a subjective self-conscious community that establishes criteria for in- or
exclusion using cultural symbols in order to differentiate themselves from other groups
(Brass 1991, p.18-20)[3]. Ethno-nationalism and state-centred or
generated nationalism can therefore both be seen as subtypes of a general identity
creating process, defined as a process whereby the subjective meaning of a number of
symbols is intensified, and as a strive for obtaining a multisymbol congruence among
a group of people defined initially by one or more central symbols, whether those symbols
are ethnic attributes or loyalty to a particular state (Brass 1991, p.20). Brass instrumental approach is made
clear when he states that ethnicity can be activated in special contexts or/and at
specific times. The main point is that the formation or politicisation of ethnicity is
seen as a process created in the dynamics of �lite competition. The elites make use of
the attributes of the ethnic groups as resources, intensifies them and thereby creates a
political identity, which is used in the competition for political power and economic gain
(Brass 1991, p.15-16). Basically he sees ethnic groups as mobilised by disgruntled elites
to a growing sense of group solidarity (Brass 1991, p.41). Hence ethnic groups, or rather
their elites, are using the ethnicity to put demands to the political system in order to
improve their status, economic situation, civil rights or educational/job possibilities. 2.3 Nationalism as a Modern
Phenomenon
In continuation of the view of nationalism
as a political doctrine it is easy to view nationalism as a modern phenomenon, something
understood in connection to the emergence of the modern centralising state. To illustrate what nationalism has meant
in Europe, Gellner asks the reader to imagine two ethnographic maps, one drawn up before
the age of nationalism and one after. The first would be a chaos of different colours,
where no clear pattern would be found and where it would be difficult to make out, where
one colour stops and the other takes over. In the other the colours are clearly separated,
neat flat surfaces clearly separated from each other and there is little if any ambiguity
or overlap. If one shifts to reality, one will discover that the prevailing part of the
political authority has been placed in a certain kind of institution - the modern
centralising nation state. This always identifies itself with one kind of culture and one
style of communication within its boundaries. In order to exist, the state is dependent of
a centralised educational system, the content of which it dictates as well as finances. If we look at the economy in a society
with such a state, it will become clear why it has to be this way. Its economy depends on
communication between the individuals and their mobility at a level it would not be
capable of maintaining, if the individuals had not been socialised into the culture of the
concerned society (Gellner 1983, p.139-140). In this way Gellner sees nationalism as
the organisation of human groups into large, centrally educated, culturally homogeneous
units. Its roots should not be found in the human psyche but in the distinctive structural
requirements of industrial society and modes of production (Gellner 1983, p.34-35). The
requirements of a mobile division of labour, and sustained, frequent and precise
communication between strangers involving a sharing of explicit meaning, transmitted in a
standard idiom and in writing when required (Gellner 1983, p.34). Also Hobsbawm views nations as new
phenomenon, invented and socially produced, it belongs exclusively to a particular,
and historically recent, period. It is a social entity only insofar as it relates to a
certain kind of modern territorial state, the nation-state, but it is
not exclusively a function of this. The emergence of nationalism should also be seen in
the context of a particular stage of technological and economic development
(Hobsbawm 1990, p.9-10), whereby he is in line with Gellners thesis. Anderson however, as we shall see, holding
a primarily cultural understanding of nationalism, also relates the emergence of
nationalism to the processes of modernisation and the emergence of capitalism, but this he
relates to the weakening of two cultural systems. That of the kings divine right and the
religious community. In this way the imagination of the nation was made possible by
changes of some fundamental cultural conceptions. Anderson puts special emphasis on the
role of print-capitalism, which made it possible for a rapidly growing numbers of
people to think about themselves, and to relate themselves to others. Although he speaks
of cultural systems he puts emphasis on some structural changes, in connection with the
processes of modernisation, which made it possible to imagine the new community. Brass stresses specifically the relevance
of the nature of the modern centralising nation-state in explaining ethnic conflict. He
writes that there is nothing natural or inevitable about ethnic conflict, the answers
should be found in the relations between the centralising state and the regional ethnic
elites (Brass 1991, p.242 and 244). Brass sees the state, especially in societies
undergoing secularisation, modernisation and industrialisation, as both a resource and as
a distributor of resources and at the same time as promoting new values. Therefore, the
state and its policies are described as a potential advantage for some groups and
societies and a threat for others, especially for local elites and societies whose values
differ (Brass 1991, p.272). The processes of modernisation in a
society consists of a dual fight for control of resources and values between bureaucracies
and political organisations at the centre and between the elites of the centre and local
elites. The ethnic elites function as effective rivals to the civil and military
bureaucracies because of their ability to mobilise popular support, exactly because they
control symbolic resources and values on the grounds of their cultural fundament. In this
way the necessity for local collaborators arises - in the sense that the state makes
alliances and coalitions with local ethnic elites, both because of state intrusion by its
centralising policies, but also because of the fact that the ethnic groups pose a threat
to the state due to their position as competing systems. As to the fight over resources Brass
states that the objective existence of disparity is an indispensable explanation of ethnic
conflict but not an explanation in itself. The mere presence of disparity is not enough to
explain or produce a nationalistic movement, nor can it explain why dominant groups
develop a such (Brass 1991, p.41-42). In Brass understanding elites and competition
among elites and the relation to the state are the essential elements in ethnic group
conflict and political mobilisation. All other factors, including size and richness of
available cultural symbols, regional economic disparities or the like, are just background
material for the elites to draw from to their aims. Without the elites these differences
or disparities will just vanish or be accepted or maybe be the cause of sporadic or
isolated incidents of conflict or disorder. In this way Brass explains the rise of
Croatian nationalism, not as a feeling of relative deprivation or deprivation at all, but
due to the fact that there existed advantages for the �lite that could be gained by
emphasising Croatian distinctiveness (Brass 1991, p.44). Basically Brass puts emphasis on the
interaction between the state and the peripheral ethnic elites in times of modernisation
and drastic changes in the society, such as changes in the political context and in the
balance of the centre-periphery relations. Ethnic conflicts emerge especially under three
types of conditions: ...during transfer of power from colonial to post-colonial
states, during succession struggles, and at times when central power appears to be
weakening or the balance in centre-periphery relations appears to be changing (Brass
1991, p.244). 2.4 Nationalism as a Cultural
Phenomenon
Other authors put more emphasis in
explaining nationalism from the angle of fulfilling a basic need in people, meaning from a
more actor-oriented angle. Benedict Anderson, who takes the task of explaining, what it is
that make people love and die for nations - as well as hate and kill for it, finds it
necessary, like Gellner and Hobsbawm, to understand how nations have come into historical
being. In this sense you can say that he too holds a structuralistic historical approach.
Unlike the other theorists, Anderson looks closely at the emotional power nationalism
holds, and in this way he states that it would, I think, make things easier if one
treated it (nationalism) as if it belonged with kinship and
religion, rather than with liberalism or fascism (Anderson 1983, p.5). Andersons definition of the nation
as an imagined political community - imagined as both inherently limited and
sovereign (Anderson 1983, p.6) reveals that he as well puts emphasis on the
political aspect of nationalism and the importance of the emergence of the modern
centralising state. But unlike especially Gellner, he seeks to understand the emotional
appeal and cultural nature of nationalism, this is especially underlined in his
descriptions on the effects of print-capitalism, as a structural condition, but in the
light of making it possible to imagine the community in a different way. Theories, like Gellners, are good
for explaining the changes in linguistic and cultural standardisation that happened during
the transition from agrarian society to industrial society. Gellners theoretical
construction suffers however, from a very instrumentalist understanding of nationalism as
such. It is as if he has never known the feeling or felt the need to confront with people
that have felt it. Gellner lacks the ability to explain the emotional appeal nationalism
holds. Therefore, as much as you can agree with his definition of nationalism as a
political principle, which holds that the political and the national unit should be
congruent as much you can disagree with his definition of nationalist sentiment as
the feeling of anger aroused by the violation of this principle and a
nationalist movement as one acurated by a sentiment of this kind (Gellner 1983,
p.1). The imagination of the community plays a
central role in Andersons understanding of nationalism. The community of the nation
reaches beyond social and religious layers in society. In spite of inequality and
exploitation, the community is always imagined as a deep horizontal brotherhood. Thus
Anderson looks at the strength of the community as a brotherhood, assuming a common past
and destiny, in the course of which enormous sacrifices in the name of the nation was made
in wars. Nationalism is strong as opposed to ideologies because these are not capable of
giving answer to human sufferings and basic questions such as the meaning of death,
illness and life in general. In this way nationalism is viewed as a
transverse, cultural phenomenon which offers a feeling of community and identity in the
nation which religion previously could offer (Anderson 1983, p.12). The nation is
eternal, it offers a feeling of common destiny - it is worth dying for.
Anderson points to the fact that nearly every West-European nation has a tomb for
the Unknown Soldier. A symbol of the continuance of the nation, in spite of the fact
that the soldier is dead and even not in the tomb. Because of the nature of the nation,
the soldier is so to say still alive and the sacrifice that he made for his country is not
forgotten (Anderson 1983, p.9). This is also the case when one refers to his homeland.
This often happens in the style and vocabulary of kinship: Motherland, Vaterland, Patria,
etc. These terms refer to something natural that one is naturally - by birth -
tied to (Anderson 1983, p.143). In everything natural there is always
something not chosen, things are just as they are. You are a part of the above-mentioned
community of destiny. As a result, the nation can appeal for sacrifice and patriotism. Anderson makes in this way a comparison
between family and patriotism/nation-ness. The nation calls for unselfish love and
solidarity. This is what the family traditionally has been conceived as being the domain
of. His conclusion is that patriotism is the same form of unselfishness, and that the
nation therefore - via peoples patriotism - can make people sacrifice their life in
war. Another important exponent of viewing
nationalism as a cultural phenomenon rather than as an ideology or form of politics is
Anthony D. Smith. According to him national identity provides for the individual a
satisfying answer to the problem of personal oblivion, through the creation of
a community of history and destiny which saves the individual from obliviation
and restores collective faith (Smith 1991, p.160-161). He stresses the close relationship between
the family, the ethnic community and the nation. He sees nationalism as a collective
cultural identity, a sense of continuity over generations of a given cultural unit (the
myth of common descent, rather than actual continuity of cultural patterns), as shared
memories of earlier events, and as the idea of a collective destiny entertained by each
generation. The pattern is the myths, symbols, collective memories and values which bind
the generations together and demarcates the outsiders (Smith 1991, p.25). In
this way it is as to become part of a political super-family, to realise the
ideal of fraternity. Nations are in this way understood simply as families writ
large, a large sum of many interrelated families, brothers and sisters all (Smith
1991, p.162). However, Smith still terms nationalism as
an ideological movement, but here it is important to stress that he sees it as an ideology
of the nation rather than the state. Smiths definition of the nation, as a
named human population sharing an historic, common myths and historical memories, a
mass, public culture, a common economy and common legal rights and duties for all
members...sets it clearly apart from any conception of the state (Smith
1991, p.14). In this connection it is also interesting that his definition of nationalism
does not necessarily include the wish for statehood but for maximal control of the
homeland and its resources. But still this definition makes it possible to see national
identity and nationalism as multi-dimensional and hence easily connected to political
ideologies like liberalism, fascism, and communism. Furthermore Smith does not deny the close historical relationship
between the state and the nation, but he sees them as two clearly separated concepts.
Nationalism in this way is seen as a sort of culture rather than a political doctrine and
should not be mixed up with the fact that states use nationalism for legitimising
purposes, which they have done and still do. The main difference then between Smith and
Anderson is that Smith ascribes nationalism a cultural inner core while Anderson
consistently views nationalism as an abstract phenomenon. 2.5 Nationalism as a Primordial
Phenomenon
As noted above most of the theoreticians
of nationalism understand the phenomenon in connection with the emergence of the modern
centralising state and the related processes of modernisation. However, some of the
authors put, more or less, emphasis on the so-called primordial aspects of nationalism in
their understanding of the phenomenon. Primordialism means that the modern nation is seen
as a representation of age-old cultural patterns. A modern form of group belonging
formerly expressed in clans, kinship and ethnic groups. In this lies the understanding
that nationalism should be seen as an expression for the human need of group belonging
(which we also can recognise from Anderson). The rhetoric of nationalists themselves is
the closest we come a pure primordial understanding. From this perspective nations are
regarded as natural phenomena of great antiquity, to this picture we can add the
nationalist myths of the nation waiting, Sleeping Beauty-like, to be awaken
from its slumber, to fulfil its predestined goal of attaining freedom and autonomy
(Anderson 1983, p.195 and Gellner 1983, p.48). As we have seen, Gellner views nationalism
and nations as creations, and in describing them as such, he pictures the nationalist
rhetorics and myths well. The myth of the nation as nature-given and eternal is false, he
states, and goes on by writing that Nations as a natural, God-given way of
classifying men, as an inherent though long-delayed political destiny, are a myth;
nationalism, which sometimes takes pre-existing cultures and turns them into nations,
sometimes invents them, and often obliterates pre-existing cultures: that is a
reality... (Gellner 1983, p.48-49). In Smiths book National
Identity he focuses exactly on the continuity between pre-modern ethnic identity and
the modern nations. This puts him within the primordial school, although, as we shall see,
he holds a more differentiated view. Contrary to the modernist, who claims that nations
are inventions, Smith stresses that nationalism is not more invented than other forms of
culture, ideology or social organisation (Smith 1991, p.71). Smith argues for a view in
between the primordialists and modernists, stating that an ethnie (the French word he uses
for ethnic communities) is formed, neither by actual ancestry nor by lines of physical
descent (which is irrelevant). But through a sense of continuity, shared memory and
collective destiny. Ethnies are so to speak formed by lines of cultural affinity,
expressed in distinctive myths, memories, symbols, and values which are maintained and
retained by a given cultural unit of the population (Smith 1991, p.29). Collective cultural identity, he writes,
refers not to a uniformity of elements over generations but rather, to a sense of
continuity on the part of successive generations of a given cultural unit of population,
to shared memories of earlier events and periods in the history of that unit and to
notions entertained by each generation about the collective destiny of that unit and its
culture (Smith 1991, p.25). Smith is of the opinion that there is a
relation between the modern nation and the premodern ethnie; ...many nations have
been formed in the first place around a dominant ethnie, which annexed or attracted other
ethnies or ethnic fragments into the state to which it gave a name and a cultural
charter (Smith 1991, p.39). But the connection is complex because of the fact that
not all modern nations are based on this, i.e. United States of America, Australia and
most of the African post-colonial states. Despite this fact, Smith states that there
are some reasons why, the origins of the nation should be looked for in the pre-modern
ethnic ties. First of all, the first nations were formed on the basis of pre-modern ethnic
cores, and because they were so powerful and culturally influential, they became models
for other cases of nation-formation. The second reason is that the ethnic model of the
nation became increasingly popular and widespread, because it fitted so well to the
premodern demotic kind of community that had survived into the modern era. The ethnic
model was hence sociologically fertile. Third, even in the cases where there were no
ethnic antecedents of importance, nations anyway need to create a certain coherent
mythology and symbolism around a historical-cultural community (Smith 1991, p.41-41). 2.6 Ethnicity
In this section I would like to expand on
the issue of ethnicity. First of all the difference between ethnicity and nationalism, an
ethnic group and a nation. This mainly because of the fact that the chosen theoretical
writings I have used so far are not specifically focused on ethnicity. Secondly from my
point of view they also generally lack, what one might call, a social comprehension of
ethnicity and national identity. I have therefore allowed myself to seek some answers from
an anthropological perspective using mainly Thomas Hylland Eriksen Ethnicity and
Nationalism. Basically the difference between nations
and ethnic groups is seen to be a question of size but that the structural composition and
functioning are of the same kind. Hylland Eriksen states that yes they are kindred
conceptions but a distinction is worthwhile because of the relationship to the modern
state (Eriksen 1993, p.98-99 and 105). In this respect you can speak of the
difference between the notions of nation and ethnic group corresponding to the earlier
mentioned distinction (section 2.1), between the nation seen as either political-civic or
organic-cultural. In the organic-cultural the nation is defined in ethnic terms. In the
political-civic the nation is defined in political terms inseparably connected to the
notion of the nation state. But as we have seen, nations defined
initially political-civic still are not to be understood exclusively as political
organisations. They also have had and have to draw on symbolic resources in order to
uphold a collective identity. Nations are thus seldom defined only by citizenship, but
also by culture. Nations can contain different ethnic groups or be defined mainly or only
by the dominant ethnic group. Both nationalism and ethnicity strives for and stresses the
cultural similarity of their adherents, but in different ways. When we speak of this in
relation to the two ideal types, the important difference is as mentioned, that the
political-civic, is unifying and expanding, striving for inclusion. So even though we are
dealing with ideal types, in the way that they are seldom found in a pure form, this does
not make the distinction irrelevant. The governments of Mandela and Yeltsin are not
nationalistic in the same way, as the governments of Tudjman or Landsbergis, who contrary
to the first mentioned, have had an exclusive understanding of the nation and thus have
agitated for fragmentation and restriction. The term ethno-nationalism should
therefore be used to refer to the claim, of an ethnic group or a state, to an ethnically
homogenous state. The conflictual aspect lies thus in the fact that many states or ethnic
groups do strive towards this goal or behave as if it was the case. In this way
nationalism differentiate from ethnicity by its relation to the state, even though Smith
have a point in not including the state in his definition of the nation and speak of
maximal control of the homeland and its resources. Smith is one of the few who include this
in his definition of the nation, whereas most others have it as the major difference
between nation and ethnic group. In this way ethnicity is exactly not necessarily about
attaining statehood. The statistics of the former Soviet Union spoke of 104 nations
comprising the union, they were in fact ethnic groups in as much as they didnt want
full independence (Eriksen 1993, p.119). On the other hand however, one could also state,
as Hylland Eriksen point out, that the phenomenon of ethnicity like nationalism is
inseparable from the notion of the modern centralising territorial nation state since this
has meant a politicisation of culture (Eriksen 1993, p.125). Ethnic groups become relevant
because of the homogenising nature of the modern centralising nation state. Still we have to account for the
differences between nation and ethnic group or what Anthony Smith calls an ethnie, the
latter, according to Smith, being a premodern basis on which most nations are formed. Both
Smith and Brass describes levels of ethnicity, from ethnic category through ethnic
community to nations, which imply a focus on consciousness but also more or less on
objective criteria. Objective criteria - since the starting point of this ladder is a set
of criteria - which separate the different groups from each other. Smiths starting
point is the ethnic category, which by others are seen to constitute a
separate entity without any special self-consciousness to ethnie defined by
believed common cultural traits and a self-consciousness and finally to the nation. Brass
also operates with the difference between ethnic category and ethnic
community defined by ethnicity as self-consciousness and then finally the nation.
The ethnic category being defined by some more or less objective but chosen criteria,
amongst many possible, which through the ethnic community to the nation increases in
number as well as subjective meaning. Hylland Eriksen also operates with
different levels of ethnicity but with another agenda. That is looking specifically on the
relationship between groups and in this way showing that ethnicity can have different
social importance, be up- or downgraded according to the social context (Eriksen 1993,
p.41). Brass also states, as we have seen, that
ethnicity can be activated in special context or/and at specific times. The difference is
however, that Hylland Eriksen has a more social angel than, as Brass, a mere instrumental
angel to this. Before entering this discussion I have to dwell a bit on Hylland
Eriksens overall position on ethnicity, which will shed some light on the subject. Hylland Eriksen defines ethnicity as a
special kind of consciously communicated and manifested cultural identity. An identity
building on the consciousness of being different. However, cultural difference between two
groups is not the decisive feature of ethnicity, only in so far as cultural differences
are perceived as being important, and are made socially relevant do relationships have an
ethnic element. Ethnicity is rather constituted through social interaction than cultural
content (Eriksen 1993, p.18 and p.36). Hence ethnic groups does necessarily emerge because
of contacts between groups. Ethnicity is therefore an aspect of a social relation between
groups (Eriksen 1993, p.11-12). To speak of an isolated ethnic group is like to hear a
sound from one hand clapping as he writes (Eriksen 1993, p.1). Hylland Eriksen also draws on the work of
Frederik Barth from 1969, which can be characterised as a watershed within the study of
ethnicity. Barth precisely turned the focus from the cultural content to looking at
ethnicity as emerging in the borderland between groups. Therefore it is the boundaries -
as a social and not territorial phenomenon upon, which the focus should be put. Ethnicity
is always about culture - people or groups that subjectively maintain cultural
peculiarity. The problem is precisely that cultures, which subjectively differentiate from
each other, not always do so objectively. But when the mutual subjective understanding is
such that the groups do differ from each other, then it constitutes a social reality,
which is manifested as ethnic identity. The maintenance of ethnic boundary is therefore,
from the point of view of Barth, a social phenomenon, rather than a cultural, and
therefore it is exactly the life and movements of the boundary that must be studied and
not the cultural content. Cultural variation is rather an effect then a cause of
boundaries. Hence a focus on the social relations, the way the borders are maintained and
changed over time and in that way also how the meaning changes. This corresponds to the view on culture as
complex, something fluid and dynamic. Culture is not something that is, but something that
takes place in a constant process of change and negotiation. This also implies a view on
persons as complex entities with several social identities, which are created, undergo
change and that is activated in different social situations. In this paradigm ethnicity is
defined as fluid and negotiable. The importance varies situational. The we
category can be expanded and contracted according to the situation and the individual can
choose to emphasise different social identities at different times (Eriksen 1993,
p.20-35). Although somewhat unfair to most of the
theories, as their main focus rest upon other aspects, we may use this discussion to
criticise the body of theoretical work so far used. They have, I would not say a too
categorical view on nations and ethnic groups, but do exactly not stress this fluid,
situational and negotiable aspect of ethnicity and national identity. Most of them, as we
have seen, do emphasise the constructed aspect of ethnic and national identity but roughly
speaking I would still say that they treat nations in a too fixed and categorical manner. Thus I find this anthropological approach
by Hylland Eriksen and Barth very useful because they turn the focus on boundaries rather
than cultural content and by doing so particularly points to the fluid or situational
character of ethnicity. This opens up for a more complex view on these collective
categories. Not just as something that is not static but also not treated as a totality.
This point became very obvious to me in the field, working closely with the different UN
agencies and the OSCE. These organisations, as well as several NGOs, very often
treated the different ethnic groups almost as if they were singular actors. Thereby
playing along in the continuos entrenchment of the us and them
dichotomy. Of cause one could say to their defence
that this is exactly what nationalism and ethnicity is about, as the Croatian writer
Slavenka Draculic so nicely puts it: The problem with this nationalism is however,
that where I previously was defined by my education, profession, my thoughts, my
personality - and yes also my nationality, - I now feel deprived from all of this. I am
nothing, no longer a person. I am one of 4.5 million Croats (Draculic 1993, p.49-50,
my translation). But academically, and in the field for
that sake, it is still important to have an eye for the fact that ...identities are
never completed, never finished, that they are always as subjectivity itself is, in
process...all of us are composed of multiple social identities not of one (Stuart
Hall 1991, p.47 and p.57). In this lies the assumption that identities can crosscut one
another and sometimes even be contradictory. This opens up for not just treating these
aggregated groups as totalities, but to look at the internal role-divisioning and the
possibility for individuals to not only over- or under-communicate their ethnic or
national identity but to shift between different identities and in some instances even
change affiliation[4]. 2.7 Summing Up and Conclusions
Nationalism as we have seen above has not
one, but several meanings depending on space and time and is changeable as well.
Nationalism or rather nationalisms are multidimensional and ambiguous phenomena. Most of
the theoreticians not only emphasise one aspect of nationalism but include several
different aspects, although to a greater or lesser extend. Nevertheless nationalism can broadly be
understood as a socio-political phenomenon, as an emotional affiliation to a country
and/or a group of people, as a form of collective consciousness. I.e. the nation-state can
be understood as a territory where the population is united in a nation by the bond of
nationalism, that being mainly defined in a civic-political or in a mainly organic-ethnic
manner. But nationalism can also be attached to people or ethnic groups across or within
the framework of the state and might be expressed in demands of grades of autonomy of own
affairs or in the more extreme cases, as ours, separatism. Nationalism is a relatively modern
phenomenon, but it is a mixture of old and new, politics and culture. Nationalism would
not possess the strength in emotional appeal if it couldnt draw on the feelings of a
shared community, cultural, historical memories and fulfil a need in the individual. This
is a very important fact to note in relation to ethnic conflict; ethnic mobilisation is
only possible where these symbolic resources have been continuously maintained and
developed in order to command its emotional strength and thus function as the basis of
mobilisation. The nation is imagined and a construction, but also a social reality, and it
should not be treated as something false and unreal. The argument, that states such as the
Soviet Union or Yugoslavia are artificial implies that there are
natural nations. As we have seen the nation is a modern phenomenon, all nation
states are artificial, i.e. social and political constructions. In fact
only 10 per cent of states can claim to be true nation-states, in
the sense that the boundaries of the state coincide with the nation, defined ethnically
(Smith 1991, p.15). And then again ethnicity is, as we also have seen, no less imagined,
but also a social phenomenon. Culture is not something, which is but something we
do. Although I agree up to a point, that
contrary to many nationalist ideologies, it is not nations that make states, it is at the
same time important not to reverse the argument and simply claim the opposite like
Hobsbawm does, when he writes that Nations do not make states and nationalisms but
the other way around (Hobsbawm 1990, p.10). Nations can be developed without the
agencies of the state and strive for statehood. One should not only see nations as
creations, or something made imaginable by the elites of the state-apparatus. This can
also happen through ethnic elites without a state-structure at hand. Here it is often
intellectuals or academics that are having an important role in shaping and maintaining
the symbolic resources of the group. But it is a point worth stressing, in the spirit of
Brass that this is often happening exactly as a consequence of the policies of the modern
centralising nation state. Already now we can thus draw some
conclusions. Ethnic conflict does not steam from old ancient hatreds. Ethno-national
identities are a modern phenomenon. Multinational or heterogeneous states are not
artificial constructions. The idea of the nation is artificial - a construction or an
imagination - a social reality - yes - but the idea of the homogeneous nation-state is an
illusion. The fact is that 90 percent of present days states are ethnic heterogeneous
makes homogeneity an illusion. And this illusion or strive towards homogeneity is the
conflictual aspect - not heterogeneity. Finally it should be mentioned that
despite the acknowledged strength in the emotional appeal of nationalism and its spread as
a principle all over the world, most of the authors however, agree with the point, that
nationalism is theoretically and ideologically weak, especially due to its abstract and
multidimensional character. In this way Anderson notes the
philosophical poverty and incoherence of nationalism (Anderson 1983, p.5). But this
emptiness also reflects the strength of nationalism (besides its emotional appeal), which
lies in its chameleon-like nature and its facility in combing with other issues and
ideologies (Smith 1991, p.144). Nationalism ...once created, they (different forms
of early nationalisms) became modular, capable of being transplanted, with
varying degrees of self-consciousness, to a great variety of social terrains, to
merge and be merged with a correspondingly wide variety of political and ideological
constellations (Anderson 1983, p.4). Because of the emptiness, it becomes
possible to fill the void with other elements like ideologies and political programmes. So
the conclusion must be that in order for nationalism to have success it needs more than
cultural differences it must be attached to political questions. As Gellner writes,
nationalism is not as strong as it seems like, who for the simplicity of his argument
mentions language as the criteria for culture, and states that then we have 8000 potential
nationalisms but only around 200 states (Gellner 1983, p.44-45). Cultural, national, and
linguistic etc. differences are constituent parts of nationalism, but in themselves not
enough to produce nationalism. As even Smith writes ...national aspirations tend to
combine with other non-national economic, social or political issues, and the power of the
movement often derives from this combination (Smith 1991, p.145). In further continuation of this it is a
theoretical point that an analysis of ethno-national conflicts must be contextual. The
specificity of the individual ethnic conflict is thus interesting, i.e. socio-economic,
historic, political etc. conditions and relations. At the same time I want to stress that
one should not only focus on rational calculations in an understanding of ethnic conflict.
The power of nationalism lies in the combination of the rational with the
irrational. You might see the irrational as being the fuel of nationalism and
the rational the catalyst. In this way the imagination of the community, the feeling of
belonging, the shared myths, collective memories of earlier events in history, symbols
etc. should be understood as the irrational fuel of nationalism in order to give it or
uphold its emotional strength. [1] Based
on Smith 1991, p.80-81. [2] This figure is made on the basis of Smith 1991, Hobsbawm
1990 and Marlene Wind 1992, p.41-51. [3] I
will return to a closer definitional discussion of ethnic groups and ethnicity in section
2.6. [4] The latter part of this section I owe a great deal from the
article by Stuart Hall, Old and New Identities, Old and New Ethnicities.
|